Introduction
If I may begin on a personal note, it has
taken me more than 30 years to understand why the evolutionary biology of aging
is not adequately understood by the majority of gerontologists, to say nothing
of the overwhelming majority of the non-biologists who are interested in the
problem of aging. It's not that we evolutionists haven't tried. In my own
case, I have repeatedly tried to convey the evolutionary approach to the
gerontological community, in both books and articles, across a variety of
levels and venues. During the last three decades, I have developed some
understanding of the great conceptual gulf between gerontology and evolutionary
biology. In the last few years, as the evolutionary biology of aging has been
revolutionized by a deeper understanding of the Hamiltonian foundations of
aging and late life [1], I have been particularly pessimistic about bridging
this gulf, because the evolutionary theory and experimentation in this area
have become yet more abstruse, compared to the intuitively more digestible evolutionary biology of aging that we had circa 1990 [2].
But I think I have now found a possible solution to this communication
problem, a solution that might bridge the gulf between evolutionary biologists
and the gerontological community. This solution is the concern of the present
article; ideally it will help resolve a "two cultures" problem that has
afflicted, and indeed impaired, gerontology for more than a century. In
addition, as a secondary issue, I believe that the explanatory breakthrough
that I offer here should help the gerontological community see the cogency of
the intuitive disquiet that many of them feel about recent attempts to "end" or
"cure" aging, such as the SENS proposal of de Grey [3]. I will begin by
stating my central thesis baldly. The rest of the article will then attempt to
explain and unpack this thesis for those who aren't evolutionary biologists.
Species that have distinguishable adults enjoy early adult health
because of adaptations built by natural selection acting over entire genomes,
adaptations that are the cumulative product of many millions of years of
evolution building vast libraries of adaptive genomic information. These
adaptations are fine-tuned according to the recent evolutionary histories of
populations of these species, where this fine-tuning involves thousands of
nucleotide base-pairs distributed across entire genomes with effects that are
typically both pleiotropic and epistatic across component adaptive functions.
When forces of natural selection acting on the physiological processes that
underlie adaptation progressively weaken at later adult ages, as they must in
all organisms with ovigerous reproduction according to Hamiltonian theory
[1,4], there is a reduction in the adaptive genomic information required
for survival and reproduction at those ages. This reduction in genomic
information then leads to innumerable and pervasive failures of physiological
tuning at later ages, including dysfunctional allocative signaling and
cumulative cell damage, among many other types of adaptive failure. Since
adaptation involves the careful tuning of functions at every level, from
molecule to cell to tissue to organ to overall bodily integration, the failure
of adaptation necessarily will take place at all of these levels as
well. This is what the absence of the required adaptive genomic information
necessarily produces at later adult ages.
Nonetheless, it is easy for evolution by natural
selection to build the adaptive genomic information-base required to sustain
healthspan radically. There are no absolute physiological barriers to it doing
so. This is dramatically revealed by the following: (i) the non-aging species
in which the forces of natural selection never fall; (ii) the non-aging germ
lines of all species that are not undergoing evolutionary genomic meltdown; and
(iii) the ease with which experimental evolution can slow aging when the forces
of natural selection are manipulated in the laboratory. More accurately,
these statements are respectively better rendered as follows: (i) adaptation
is maintained at all ages in species in which the forces of natural selection
never fall; (ii) germ lines are indefinitely sustainable in species that are
not undergoing evolutionary genomic meltdown; and (iii) the genomic information
required for prolonged age-specific adaptation is easily produced by outbred
laboratory populations in which the forces of natural selection are
artificially sustained at high levels at later ages.
I will now set about explaining these
ideas step-by-step, in effect supplying a brief tutorial in adaptational
genomics with particular relevance to the problem of aging.
Adaptation and the genome
The chief way in which biologists first learn about the genetic basis
of evolutionary change is with simple examples like the substitution of melanic
alleles at pigmentation loci in the case of Lepidopteran industrial melanism.
I have used this pedagogical cliché in an evolution textbook myself [5]. This
example makes it seem as if natural selection characteristically works by
targeting a single gene, with evolution achieving a simple substitution of one
allele for another. Another classic textbook example of natural selection is
the sickle-cell hemoglobin polymorphism, in which heterozygotes for the
sickling and normal alleles have both resistance to malaria and reasonable
erythrocyte structure, most of the time. Again, this simple example suggests
the action of natural selection to solve adaptive problems using alleles of
large effect at a single locus.
Unfortunately, these examples are wholly misleading. In most cases of
a strong phenotypic response to selection, in either nature or the laboratory,
there are a large number of loci involved. It was precisely this problem that
was at the root of many of Darwinism's problems incorporating Mendelian
genetics, before R.A. Fisher created quantitative genetics in 1918 [6].
Quantitative genetics is the tool that evolutionary geneticists, and
significantly plant and animal breeders as well, use to deal with the
inheritance of "quantitative characters" or "complex traits." Conversely, when
we have cases in which natural selection maintains genetic variation, as in the
case of the alcohol dehydrogenase locus in Drosophila melanogaster, the
selective mechanisms that underlie such polymorphism are often remarkably
obscure. That is, unlike the textbook cases of industrial melanism and
sickle-cell anemia, the relationship between natural selection and the genome
is characteristically "many-to-many," with numerous loci and complex phenotypic
effects of selection being the norm. This is why the study of the genetic
basis of evolutionary change is so difficult [7,8].
In a few cases, we can find simple connections between the genome and
particular phenotypes, but these are not representative. This should not be
surprising. Any allelic difference that can improve three or four characters
will be favored by natural selection, possibly even if it has deleterious
effects on one or two other characters that have less net impact on Darwinian
fitness. Alleles are selected on the basis of their average effects on the
entire adaptive phenotype, as quantified by Darwinian fitness, over the range
of genotypic backgrounds in which they occur.
Even though we find it easier to imagine that a gene is "for" one
attribute or another, evolution by natural selection can exploit pleiotropic
effects across multiple characters whenever they arise. It isn't constrained
by our limited understanding, or any need to be elegant. Evolution is
genomically complex. It builds adaptations by accumulating information of
great genomic and functional complexity over millions of years, indeed billions
of years. That is, adaptations reflect the long-term accretion of useful
genomic information, information that functionally manifests itself in the
fine-tuning of networks of interacting elements, both proteins and RNAs of
widely varying sizes and roles. That is why superoxide dismutase proteins can
be found in so many different organisms; superoxide dismutases are very useful
enzymes in vast numbers of different species, in each of which they undergo
further fine-tuning in order to improve their operation in the particular
physiological networks that underlie the survival and reproduction of members
of that particular species.
Aging: what happens when adaptation goes away
As Weismann and other evolutionary biologists have realized over the last
century and more [9], when natural selection pays attention to survival to, and
reproduction at, later ages it is trivial for evolution to build adaptations
that will enable organisms to do both of these things. Thus it is easy for
evolutionary biologists to deliberately produce organisms with slowed or
postponed aging, as our publications have shown since 1980 [1,4]. All we have
to do is extend the period during which the forces of natural selection act
with full force. Furthermore, it is clear that this entails genetic and
functional changes involving many loci [10].
Conversely, what gerontology normally
does is characterize the breakdown of age-specific adaptation, even though most
gerontologists don't think of themselves as evolutionary biologists. Failing
to take the adaptational genome-wide foundations of aging can lead to numerous
problems of experimental design and interpretation. For example,
gerontologists may worry about whether or not they should be studying the
maintenance of fertility and other adaptive functions, such as competitive
ability, that are of no direct relevance to the survival of isolated
individuals. Is, for example, a sterile fruit fly or a castrated salmon that
lives much longer actually an example of slowed aging? What about a dwarf
mouse that can only be kept alive with a "companion nurse" mouse, to keep it
warm? Or a nematode that lives much longer in one laboratory protocol, but
which has impaired survival or competitive function under other laboratory
conditions [11]? These paradoxes arise because, in studying aging, gerontologists are
studying the genome-wide breakdown of adaptation. The study of adaptation over
entire genomes is laden with both conceptual and experimental complexities. I
now give some typical examples of relevance to the study of aging. These
complexities illustrate the extent to which standard gerontological experiments
are entangled with issues from evolutionary biology.
(1) Inbreeding depression tends to degrade adaptation at every age. This
makes the study of heavily inbred laboratory animals particularly inappropriate
for research on aging, because aging is a phenomenon which hinges on the loss
of adaptation with adult age. Inbred animals will show impairments of
adaptation at every age, obscuring the essential feature of aging as a period
of progressively impaired adaptation that follows a period of adequate
adaptation.
(2) Genotype-by-environment interactions arise when organisms are
assayed in different environments, particularly environments that are
evolutionarily novel [12]. In the context of aging research, this can make
genetic effects on longevity difficult to reproduce when protocols are changed
[13]. More profoundly, studying the loss of adaptation in an organism that has
not already adapted to the laboratory setting employed in an experiment will
obscure what is going on in its aging, functionally, genetically, and
physiologically.
(3) The adaptive "costs of reproduction" underlie the well-known
antagonistic pleiotropy mechanism for the evolution of aging [14]. The costs
of reproduction can also supply a ready way to generate extended lifespan,
simply by reducing fecundity [15]. Thus evolutionary biologists expect that
experimental manipulations which attenuate reproduction will often increase
longevity, but because this involves trading one adaptation for another, we do
not regard the resulting demography as a case of slowed or postponed aging.
(4) Significantly, these last two genetic mechanisms can interact,
genotype-by-environment interaction making it difficult to detect genetic
trade-offs, even when gerontologists are trying to find them [11]. This
difficulty will be still greater when gerontologists are not particularly keen
to find evidence for such trade-offs.
(5) "Longevity mutants" will characteristically suffer from adverse
pleiotropic effects in at least some environments, because generally superior
"longevity assurance" mutants will be favored in nature. Vastly more mutations
will have been generated in the evolution of any species than we will ever
produce in our laboratories in the comparatively short-term and small-scale
mutation screens that we can perform. Generally beneficent alleles should have
already been fixed in the course of evolution by natural selection, since they
would be key adaptive substitutions.
Aging is not a disease
There are those who seek to have the NIH declare that aging is "a
disease," so that the FDA can review applications for pharmaceutical status of
agents that claim to "cure this disease." There is no question that
individuals who suffer from either juvenile or adult onset progerias, be they
Hutchinson-Gilford's progeria or Werner's syndrome, are indeed suffering from
diseases. They have well-defined spectra of pathologies that are due to single
genetic differences. Pharmaceuticals or somatic gene engineering interventions
can usefully target such genetic diseases, and are worthy of FDA approval if
they work well.
What the rest of us have is a failure of natural selection to build the
adaptations required for our continued survival and reproduction. As such,
while there is a well-defined underlying evolutionary cause, the spectrum of
aging pathologies that we suffer are multifarious and the loci that are
responsible for them are numerous and sometimes even diffuse in their
responsibility, just like the loci that are responsible for most of our
adaptations.
Aging is not a well-defined disease. If such an "aging disease"
terminology were adopted, it would be just as reasonable to say that wolves
suffer from the disease of lacking adaptations to survive in human habitats,
unlike dogs, which do have such adaptations. What then is the cure for the
wolf disease?
Nor is aging merely cumulative damage
Part-whole confusions are commonplace targets of logical training.
Aging can result in cumulative damage without itself being nothing more than
cumulative damage, unless the term "damage" is inappropriately broadened to
mean anything that is involved in aging. This would lead to as many confusions
as redefining the term "disease" to include aging.
Yet the field of gerontology has assumed
that some type(s) of inexorable damage or cumulative disruption is the entire
source of aging, from its inception with Aristotle to the free-radical theory
of aging to the recently developed rationale for SENS [3,16]. This assumption
began to unravel thanks to the work of Carey et al. [17] and Curtsinger et al.
[18], which first showed the demographic cessation of aging. These
trailblazing publications set evolutionary biologists to work re-evaluating
their interpretation of the functional impact of the plateaus in the forces of
natural selection which follow their decline [19,20]. How can the declines
with age in survival probability and fecundity cease, if aging is due to
cumulative damage? They can't. But they can in straightforward evolutionary
models [19,21].
The conundrum of aging coming to a stop, and its resolution using
evolutionary theory [19,21] and experimental evolution [e.g. 22], reveals yet
again how the foundations of gerontology actually lie within evolutionary
biology. Puzzles like whether or not aging can possibly come to an end late in
life are readily resolved using the research tools of evolutionary biology,
both theoretical and experimental.
The attempt to "End Aging"
But things become still worse when we turn to proposals for "ending
aging," "curing the aging disease," and other recent aspirational infirmities
of the anti-aging movement. As I will now argue, it is particularly when we
turn to these hopes that it becomes obvious that gerontology needs evolutionary
foundations and tools.
Let us start with the advocates of hormone
supplementation as a cure for "the aging disease." There is at least some bare
evolutionary credibility behind such proposals, in that hormonal manipulations
are heavily implicated in the beneficial responses to castration in both animal
and plant species [23]. Hormones are indeed the master controls of
life-history, and changing their levels demonstrably has pervasive functional
effects [24]. But the problem is that antagonistic pleiotropy is the likely
mechanism behind the benefits that have been realized from hormonal
manipulation. Because reproduction is costly, limiting it hormonally should
sometimes produce longevity benefits.
Ironically, the most widely used hormone interventions in "anti-aging
medicine" involve hormone supplementation with growth hormone or sex steroids,
which experimental data and evolutionary theory both suggest will decrease
lifespan and later-life somatic functions, thanks to increased physiological
investment in costly functions related to reproduction. This couldn't be a
more ill-founded therapeutic strategy, from the standpoint of evolutionary
theory.
Then we have those pharmaceutical strategies that are based on emulating the pathways implicated in the response of lifespan
to dietary restriction, particularly sirtuin-targeting agents like resveratrol
[e.g. 25]. Again, like hormone manipulation, these pathways are heavily bound
up with the regulation of reproduction, making the curtailment of the cost of
reproduction the most likely mechanism by which the beneficial effects of
emulating dietary restriction are achieved [cf. 26]. This is a strategy in
which longevity is increased by metabolic refrigeration, pseudo-hibernation, or
curtailing functions [11]. From the standpoint of evolutionary biology, this
is, again, not an extension of the period of adaptation. It is instead trading
one set of adaptations off against another. Most people do not regard
curtailing their metabolism, cognition, affective stability or reproductive
functions as a useful approach to the problem of aging. Nonetheless, some are
willing to trade-off some of their adaptive functions for an increased
lifespan, and for them this "anti-aging" strategy will have its attractions.
Finally, we have SENS [3]. Taking "Strategies for Engineering
Negligible Senescence" literally as worded, it is impossible to object to, at
least as a technological ambition. The problems arise with the conceit that
aging is due entirely to seven types of cellular or molecular damage. For
those well-trained in medical pathology, this assertion flies directly in the
face of the remarkably diverse ways in which the aging human body manages to
get things wrong as it becomes older. Aging involves derelictions of function
at many different levels of biological organization, in strikingly
heterogeneous ways across different types of tissue and organ, as a reasonable
reading of the aging literature, medical or comparative, would show an
open-minded reader [vid. 23]. And this is just as evolutionary biologists have
long expected.
Aging is not due to the progressive
breakdown of a complex biochemical machine due to accretions of damage
afflicting an entity that could otherwise continue functioning indefinitely.
The fact that it is well within the capacity of evolution by natural selection
to produce organisms that don't age shows that there is something wrong with
this assumption. Instead, evolution by natural selection does not bother building
ovigerous organisms that can live indefinitely, because the genomically-complex
and information-laden adaptations required for indefinite survival of such
adult somata are not favored by natural selection. This results in the absence of the substantial amount of genomic information that is required to
sustain life indefinitely. It isn't damaged information, any more than the
aging body merely suffers damage during aging and nothing else. The adaptive
genomic information required for indefinite survival simply hasn't been
produced by evolution.
Extending healthspan requires extending adaptation
To evolutionary biologists, then, the problem of extending healthspan
is how to produce the adaptations required to sustain high levels of function
at later ages. Evolutionary biologists have known since the 1950's that
lifespan can be increased fairly predictably by curtailing reproduction and its
associated physiological costs and stresses. Drugs, surgery, and diet can all
have this effect. But the problem of a true extension of "a full life," or
"healthspan," is more difficult, because it is nothing less than building a new
set of later-age adaptations.
This difficult problem becomes trivially easy for us to solve when we
can control Hamilton's [1,4] forces of natural selection: when we tune these
forces up at later ages in genetically variable populations over a number of
generations, increased healthspan or, to us evolutionary biologists, prolonged
adaptation is the predictable result [2,27].
It is organisms whose evolution we can't control that pose a severe
technological problem of aging for evolutionists. Evidently, as both a
practical and an ethical matter, we can't control human evolution.
Contemporary evolutionists think of this as an impractical and morally dubious
project, contrary to the eugenicists of the early 20th Century.
On the view of aging presented here, extending human healthspan
requires that we find means by which we can emulate what natural selection has
already given us at earlier ages: a broad spectrum of adaptations that have
been produced by millions of years of fine-tuning the vast amount of
information stored in each mammalian genome. This is such a daunting prospect
that most evolutionary biologists, who generally understand the point that the
evolution of aging is founded on a failure of adaptation, regard the slowing of
human aging as an essentially intractable problem. But at least some
evolutionists who used to feel that way have now changed their minds.
Evolutionary strategies for extending human adaptation
to later ages
Experimental evolution and genomics are the technologies that have
changed the prospects for extending human adaptation to later ages, in the eyes
of some evolutionary biologists at least. I will explain how by following the
historical progression by which this possibility was conceived by evolutionary
biologists.
Experimental evolution is the technique that has best fostered the
scientific evaluation of the evolutionary theories and mechanisms of aging
[28]. Experimental evolution is an empirical approach based on setting up
conditions in which replicated populations are allowed to evolve, using either de
novo mutations [29] or standing genetic variation [30] as "fuel" for the
evolutionary process, and focused selection pressures of some type as the
"steering" for the evolutionary process [31]. Some of the first tests of the
basic Hamiltonian evolutionary theory for aging were performed using
experimental protocols in which the first age of reproduction was progressively
postponed in outbred Drosophila populations over more than ten
generations [32]. For the last 30 years, such evolution experiments have
repeatedly corroborated the evolutionary theory of aging [28].
But more importantly, for the present purpose, these experiments have
produced a variety of experimentally evolved populations in which adaptation
has been sustained well on to later ages. That is, organisms with slowed aging
have been derived from organisms with a faster rate of aging; to use the
language of adaptational biology, we have been able to extend the period of
adequate adaptation from early life to later life. Comparing the extended-adaptation Drosophila with their matched controls has allowed useful physiological
and genetic analysis of the mechanistic basis of extending adaptation [27]. In
particular, it was soon estimated that many genes were involved in this
prolongation of Drosophila adaptation, implicating a large amount of
genomic change in the re-tuning of the aging process [10].
In the 1980s, evolutionary biologists did
not think longer-lived Drosophila would provide much, if any, useful
guide to the specific genomic foundations of aging in humans, because of
then-prevailing expectations among evolutionary biologists that there would be
wide divergence of genomes among phylogenetically distant species [vid. [33]].
(In this respect, the prejudices of many molecular biologists were more
accurate than those of mainstream evolutionary biologists before the advent of
genomics.) Thus it was proposed that progress in finding the right genomic and
physiological information for postponing human aging required the development
of mice with selectively postponed aging [34]. Unfortunately, while it was
shown that the same evolutionary methods as those used with Drosophila alsoworked in a small-scale mouse experiment [35], the level of replication
used in that experiment was not sufficient to make these mice promising
material for genetic or physiological analysis. Despite repeated attempts to
produce a consensus that the creation of properly replicated populations of
mice with evolutionarily extended adaptation would benefit gerontological
research, the project was never attempted [36]. This seemed to preclude any
reasonable prospect for evolutionary biology contributing to the amelioration
of human aging.
The advent of whole-genome technologies, or
"genomics," circa the year 2000 changed the situation substantially. Most
importantly, it was realized that there was far more orthology among the genes
of metazoan genomes than had been anticipated by evolutionary biologists,
particularly within the segmented bilaterian group, which includes both insects
and mammals. Genome-wide studies comparing the loci involved in Drosophila aging
with the entire human genome give estimates of orthology that are quite high,
well over 80% [37], suggesting the possibility of extrapolating from Drosophila evolutionary genomics to humans in the case of aging. This may be because
the many loci which must evolve in order to sustain adaptation at later ages
are involved in common "housekeeping" functions, such as energetic metabolism -
which has been extensively implicated in the evolution of slowed aging in fruit
flies [27], rather than lineage-specific loci, in most cases. This in turn
leads to the possibility of developing pharmaceutical and other interventions
for human aging based on research that starts with the genomic information
required to sustain adaptation, and thus health, in older fruit flies [36-39].
Naturally, any such genomic short-cut to
reverse-engineering the evolution of slowed aging from fruit flies to humans is
fraught with potential for error. Such evolutionarily deep orthologies are
sure to supply incomplete information. The originally proposed evolutionarily slowed-aging
mouse remains the best model organism for a project of this kind. But creating
it will be a demanding project, requiring years to produce fruitful results,
and substantial resources [34,39]. For the time being, the most feasible
evolutionary strategy for extending human adaptation into later years is that
based on experimental evolution with model organisms like Drosophila, particularly
because such organisms already exist and the physiological changes associated
with their slowed aging have already been studied extensively.
Conclusion: bridging the two cultures of aging research
This review evidently proposes that both the scientific foundations of
gerontology and the systematic, rather than adventitious, slowing of human
aging would benefit from the use of evolutionary theory and experimental
evolution augmented with genomics. This is because aging is properly understood
as the fading out of adaptation with adult age. As evolutionary biologists
have been studying adaptation for 150 years, and because we have an extensive
tool kit for such research [40], we evolutionists naturally think that progress
in gerontological research would be materially accelerated by the use of
evolutionary foundations and tools [2,41]. This doesn't mean gerontologists
becoming evolutionary biologists, anymore than human geneticists are all
population geneticists. But it does mean bridging the gaps between gerontology
and evolutionary biology, just as human geneticists talk and collaborate with
population geneticists.
Nor should this be construed as an argument that gerontology can do
without any of the skills that are deployed so resourcefully by mainstream
gerontologists. Evolutionary biologists have a long history, indeed as old as
Charles Darwin's original publications, of making use of all elements of
biology, both as sources of information and as sources of useful tools for their
own experiments. Evolutionary research on aging has been no exception to this
overall pattern.
But evolutionists are generally united in their impatience with
gerontological theories that are incompatible with evolutionary theory. And we
chiefly feel scorn toward "anti-aging medicine" that is based on presumptions
precisely contrary to evolutionary biology, just as we feel toward
creationism. We offer the formal foundation necessary for mathematically
sorting out much gerontological theorizing. We can supply useful experimental
strategies from our longstanding tradition of studying adaptation, and we can
demonstrably produce model organisms with extended healthspan at will. We feel
that gerontology can prosper if it makes use of these substantive contributions.
I hope that I have managed to explain to a few more gerontologists why
they should make material use of evolutionary thinking in their theoretical and
experimental research. It provides concrete foundations, not window
dressings.
I am grateful to Mikhail V. Blagosklonny
for commissioning this article and for suggested revisions. I am also grateful
to P. Shahrestani and L.G. Cabral for thoughtful improvements to the text. I
have been employed as a scientific consultant by the following corporations:
MRX Biosciences, Methuselah Flies, and Genescient. I currently own small
amounts of stock in Methuselah Flies LLC and Genescient Inc, neither of which
are publicly traded. My academic research in this area since 1976 has been
supported by too many awards, grants, and agencies to list here, although
recent support from NSF and the University of California is much appreciated.
The author has no conflict of interests to declare.